Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860)
Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860)
Certainly one of the greatest
philosophers of the 19th century, Schopenhauer seems to
have had more impact
on literature (e.g. Thomas Mann) and on people in general than
on academic
philosophy. Perhaps that is because, first, he wrote very well, simply and
intelligibly (unusual, we might say, for a German philosopher, and unusual
now for any
philosopher), second, he was the first Western philosopher to
have access to translations
of philosophical material from India, both Vedic
and Buddhist, by which he was
profoundly affected, to the great interest of
many, and, third, his concerns were with the
dilemmas and tragedies, in a
religious or existential sense, of real life, not just with
abstract
philosophical problems. As Jung said:
He was the first to speak of the suffering of the world, which visibly
and glaringly
surrounds us, and of confusion, passion, evil -- all those
things which the [other
philosophers] hardly seemed to notice and always
tried to resolve into all-embracing
harmony and comprehensiblility. Here at
last was a philosopher who had the courage to
see that all was not for the
best in the fundaments of the universe.
[Memories, Dreams, Reflections,
Vintage Books, 1961, p. 69]
Philosophers upon whom Schopenhauer did have a
strong effect, like Nietzsche and even
Wittgenstein, nevertheless could not
put him to good use since they did not accept his
moral, aesthetic, and
religious realism. Schopenhauer is all but unique in intellectual
history
for being both an atheist and sympathetic to Christianity. Schopenhauer's
system, indeed, will not make any sense except in the context of Kant's
metaphysics.
For the purposes of the Proceedings of the Friesian School,
Schopenhauer may be said
to have made three great contributions to the
Kantian tradition, which supplement the
contemporary contributions of
Fries:
He retained Kant's notion of the thing-in-itself but recognized that it could
not exist as
a separate order of "real" objects over and above the
phenomenal objects of experience.
Hence Schopenhauer's careful use of the
singular rather than the plural when referring
to the "thing-in-itself."
Kant left his "Copernican Revolution" incomplete by describing
the ordinary
objects of experience as phenomena while leaving the impression that in an
absolute sense they were only subjective, with things-in-themselves as the
"real"
objects. Schopenhauer favorably compares Kant to Berkeley, even
though both Kant and
Schopenhauer reject a true "subjective idealism" in
which objects exist in no way apart
from consciousness. Schopenhauer's point
was that, like Berkeley, phenomena are all
there are when it comes to
objects as objects. What stands over and above objects is
something else.
For Berkeley that was only God. For Schopenhauer it was the Will as
thing-in-itself.
Schopenhauer abolished Kant's machinery of synthesis through the pure
concepts of the
understanding, substituting his fourfold "Principle of
Sufficient Reason." This misses
much of the point of Kant's argument in the
First Edition Transcendental Deduction
and would not count as an advance on
Kant if it did not also abolish the mistaken idea
in Kant that Reason, as he
conceived it, could produce out of the mere formalism of
logic a substantive
content to morality, aesthetics, etc. Schopenhauer does not have a
very good
substitute when it comes to morality (as do Fries and Nelson), but he does
in aesthetics, which leads to,
Schopenhauer's strong sense of aesthetic value, to which he gives an
intuitive,
perceptual, and Platonic cast in his theory of Ideas.
Schopenhauer gave aesthetics and
beauty a central place in his thought such
as few other philosophers have done. His
aesthetic realism is a great
advance over Kant's moralistic denial of an objective
foundation for
aesthetic reality. Beyond that lies a realistic appreciation of many
religious phenomena that is superior to Kant and conformable to insights
that will later
be found in Otto and Jung. Schopenhauer could take religion
seriously in ways that
others could not because of his pessimistic rejection
of the value of life. This, indeed,
embodies its own distortions, but it is
a welcome corrective, as Jung noted, to the
shallow optimism of most other
philosophers. And it does faithfully highlight the
world-denying trend of
important religions like Christianity, Hinduism, Jainism, and
Buddhism,
which must be addressed by any responsible philosophy of religion.
Schopenhauer's metaphysics, as stated in his classic The World as Will and
Representation (Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, 1818, 1844, 1859 --
E.F.J. Payne's
English translation, Dover Publications, 1966), is structured
through a small set of
dichotomous divisions, displayed and color coded in
the following table. Schopenhauer
prided himself on the simplicity of this
in comparison to Kant, whose system he
compared to a Gothic cathedral.
Hegel's metaphysics, which produced a potentially
infinite elaboration of
Kant's threefold structures, Schopenhauer regarded as, of course,
nonsense.
THE STRUCTURE OF SCHOPENHAUER'S METAPHYSICS
THE WILL, transcendent
Thing-in-Itself, Books II & IV REPRESENTATION
THE SUBJECT, Upanishadic
Unknown Knower, Book I THE OBJECT
Plato's IDEAS, objectivity free of the
Principle of Sufficient Reason, Book III SPACE &
TIME, governed by the
Principle of Sufficient Reason, Book I
BODY, Immediate Object of the Will
EXTERNAL OBJECTS
The basic distinction in Schopenhauer's metaphysics is between
representation and the
thing-in-itself. The thing-in-itself turns out to be
will. The will is introduced in Book
II of The World as Will and
Representation, where its manifestations in nature are also
examined. That
supplies, in effect, Schopenhauer's philosophy of science, which has its
embarrassing aspects: Schopenhauer did not understand the new physics of
light and
electricity that had been developed by Thomas Young (1773-1829)
and Michael Faraday
(1791-1867). He disparaged the wave theory of light,
which Young had definitively
established, as a "crude materialism," and
"mechanical, Democritean, ponderous, and truly
clumsy" [Dover, p. 123].
Unfortunately, Schopenhauer does not seem to have understood
the evidence
for Young's discoveries about light, or even for Newton's -- he still clung
to Goethe's clever but clueless theory of colors. Schopenhauer also required
that there
be a "vital force," though that would still be part of
respectable science for a while to
come yet. Nevertheless, Schopenhauer
would have been happy to learn how his beloved
qualitates occultae would
return in force with quantum mechanics: Things like
strangeness, charm,
baryon number, lepton number, etc., are exactly the kinds of
irreducible
types he demanded.
Book IV of The World as Will and Representation is also about the will, but
now in
terms of the denial of the will. The denial of will, self, and
self-interest produce for
Schopenhauer a theory both of morality and of
holiness, the former by which
self-interest is curtailed for the sake of
others, the latter by which all will-to-live
ceases. Schopenhauer's greatest
eloquence about the evils, sufferings, and futility of life,
and its
redemption through self-denial, occur there.
On the representation side of his metaphysics, which occupies Books I and III
of The
World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer must deal with two
areas that exercise
their own claims to be considered things-in-themselves.
First, at the beginning of Book
I, comes the Subject of Knowledge.
Schopenhauer's thought there is refined by his
reading of the Upanishads,
where the Br.hadaran.yaka Upanis.ad distinguishes the
Subject of Knowledge,
the Unknown Knower, from all Objects of Knowledge, from
everything Known.
Schopenhauer accepts that distinction, and also that the Subject is
free of
the forms of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (space, time, causality, etc.).
But the subject, the knower never the known, does not lies within these
forms [i.e.
space, time, plurality]; on the contrary, it is always
presupposed by those forms
themselves, and hence neither plurality nor its
opposite, namely unity, belongs to it. We
never know it, but it is precisely
that which knows wherever there is knowledge.
[Dover, p. 5]
Since the
Upanishads themselves posit an identity of the Subject, the Atman or Self,
with Brahman, the transcendent Supreme Reality, Being itself, one could not
confess
surprise if Schopenhauer were to identify the Subject with Kant's
transcendent
thing-in-itself. He does not, however -- deciding, rather
arbitrarily it must seem, to
retain the Subject as an Unknowable side of
representation, distinct from all Objects.
In Book III of The World as Will and Representation Schopenhauer turns to his
theory
of Ideas, which he says are the same as Plato's Ideas, and which are
also free of the
forms of space, time, and causality. For Schopenhauer, it
is through the Ideas that all
beauty is manifest in art and nature. Again,
it would not be surprising if Schopenhauer
took the Ideas to be transcendent
realities, especially when that is precisely what Plato
thought about his
own Ideas; but, as with the Subject, Schopenhauer keeps them in
representation, as the nature of Objects in so far as they are free of the
Principle of
Sufficient Reason. The bulk of Book III is then occupied with
the examination of
individual forms of art, culminating in music.
The final distinction, although it is one of the earliest made, in Book I, is
that between
the body and the other objects of representation in space and
time. For Schopenhauer,
the body is known immediately and the perception of
other objects is spontaneously
projected, in a remaining fragment of Kant's
theory of synthesis and perception, from
the sensations present in the sense
organs of the body onto the external objects
understood as the causes of
those sensations. The body itself, in Book II, becomes the
most immediate
manifestation of the will, a direct embodiment of the will-to-live.
One might say that the most interesting aspect of Schopenhauer's metaphysics
consists
of the turns not taken. The reason why the Subject and the Ideas
should be held
separate from the Will sometimes seems only to be that this
is necessary to produce
the degree of pessimism that Schopenhauer requires:
The will must be blind and
purposeless; but as the Subject it would not be
blind, and as the Ideas it would consist
of all the meaning and beauty of
the Platonic World of Ideas. Indeed, Jung would later
see the process by
which his Archetypes are instantiated, in the "individuation" of the
Self
through the "transcendent function," as the means by which consciousness is
expanded and life made meaningful:
As far as we can discern, the sole purpose of human existence is to
kindle a light in
the darkness of mere being. [Memories, Dreams,
Reflections, p. 326]
Although the theory of art Schopenhauer presents in Book
III, by which the Ideas are
instantiated much like Jung's Archetypes, might
seem to describe meaning enough for
anyone's life, Schopenhauer just cannot
imagine that it is good enough. Probably it is
not, since few enough people
find meaning in life through art. Where they have always
found it is in
religion, and Schopenhauer passes on to that ground with his theory of
holy
self-denial. But not all religion is the denial of self or of life; and
Schopenhauer is
conspicuously unsympathetic with religions, like Judaism and
Islam (or, for that matter,
Confucianism and Taoism), that do not maintain
the level of world-denial that he thinks
necessary for "true" holiness. Thus
his theory fails as phenomenology of religion. only
Otto can explain
holiness in both world-affirmation and world-denial. But no one would
ever
accuse Schopenhauer of overlooking the evils of life or misunderstanding, as is
all
too common among Western intellectuals today, the motivation of
world-denying
religions.
An excellent bust of Schopenhauer by the great German sculptress, Elisabet
Ney, can
still be seen in her studio in Austin, Texas, where she and her
husband had immigrated
from Germany. After his experience sitting for the
bust, Schopenhauer is said to have
wondered if, desipte all his misogyny,
women could after all be great artists.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
------
Arthur Schopenhauer, on "the Professors of Philosophy"
The Soliloquy in Hamlet
"Schopenhauer and Freud," by Christopher Young & Andrew Brook
History of Philosophy
Philosophy of Religion
Metaphysics
Schopenhauer on Home Page
Home Page
Copyright (c) 1996, 1998 Kelley L. Ross, Ph.D. All Rights Reserved
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
------
Arthur Schopenhauer, on "the Professors of Philosophy"
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
------
The three Prefaces of The World as Will and Representation present remarkable
changes in Schopenhauer's tone. The first, from 1818, is, as Schopenhauer
says, advice
on how the book is to be read, including the instruction that
readers go to his doctoral
dissertation, on the Fourfold Root of the
Principle of Sufficient Reason, first. They
better have read Kant, also. It
is clear that Schopenhauer expects a lot from his readers.
It later becomes
clear that he doesn't get it.
A second edition of the book was not published until 1844 -- 26 years later.
Even then
there was no great demand for it, the publisher was
unenthusiastic, and, evidently,
Schopenhauer had to defray some of the costs
of publication himself. The Preface to the
second edition reflects the
disappointment that Schopenhauer had experienced during this
period. He had
given up teaching after making no headway whatsoever against Hegel's
popularity.
I constantly saw the false and the bad, and finally the absurd and the
senseless,
standing in universal admiration and honour....[Dover edition, p.
xviii]
During his last years in Berlin, his scheduled lectures were
apparently not even given,
since there were no students (he was only paid by
the student, which is why the
lectures were scheduled at all). Even after
Hegel died in 1831, the tide of Hegelianism
was still ascendant.
Schopenhauer retired to a largely uneventful, private, and solitary
life,
living off his prudently maintained inheritance.
The tone of the second preface is thus bitter and scornful. The "professors
of
philosophy" who ignored him and adored Hegel were little better than
fools to
Schopenhauer -- dishonest, self-serving, and sophistical fools at
that. But it is there
that Schopenhauer's analysis, however embittered over
his own disappointments, is
something more than just sour grapes: He
anticipates the corrupt rent-seeking that can
result when learning is wedded
to bureaucratic authority and income:
Now what in the world has such a philosophy [i.e. Schopenhauer's] to do
with that
alma mater, the good, substantial university philosophy, which,
burdened with a hundred
intentions and a thousand considerations, proceeds
on its course cautiously tacking, since
at all times it has before its eyes
the fear of the Lord, the will of the publisher, the
encouragement of
students, the goodwill of colleagues, the course of current politics, the
momentary tendency of the public, and Heaven knows what else? Or what has my
silent and serious search for truth in common with the yelling school
disputations of the
chairs and benches, whose most secret motives are always
personal aims? [ibid. p. xxvi]
Of course, the precise tack of current
"substantial university philosophy" has changed a
bit. Fear of the Lord, or
even the tendency of the public, can now be safely ignored,
since modern
fashionable thought is irreligious far beyond anything anticipated or
desired by Schopenhauer, while the whole academic community has so
esotercized and
insulated itself that the general public hasn't got a clue
what it does or even says. Safe
in their own taxpayer subsidized enclaves,
"the professors of philosophy" find that the
"goodwill of colleagues" is
supreme, with its own special, distilled version of the "course
of current
politics," since ideological conformity has become so important that it now
even has its own name: "Political Correctness."
It is not privileged information that at present it is easier to advance
in the profession
by hanging around well-known colleagues and massaging
their egos than by an effort
at articulating a fundamental disagreement.
[Tom Rockmore, on Heidegger's Nazism and
Philosophy, U. of California Press,
1997, p. 23]
The United States Constitution prohibits the granting of any
"Title of Nobility," but
tenured academia has achieved an unaccountable
status, with a secure, indeed sinecure,
living at the public purse, that
would be the envy of any nobility that might have to
ride out and gather
rents directly from the peasants. The modern IRS takes care of
that.
Teaching, the ostensive purpose of academic employment, becomes less and less
onerous, while a vast output of esoteric research, intelligible only to the
cognoscenti, is
the key to further status and privilege. Academic
conferences are now the subsidized
and tax-deductible festivals of "the
corybantic shouting with which the birth of the
spiritual children of those
of the same mind is reciprocally celebrated..." [p. xxv], usually
at the
most pleasing venues available, from Hawaii to Manhattan to Paris.
Nothing about this, therefore, would surprise Schopenhauer in the least --
let alone that
Hegel is still held in high regard, while many of his
spiritual descendants explicitly
advocate the irrationalism and incoherence
that is merely evident in Hegel's practice, not
in his own claims to
rationality.
Schopenhauer's brief third Preface, from 1859, after the influence of Hegel
had finally
faded and Schopenhauer had become somewhat recognized and
influencial, reflects some
vindication:
If I also have at last arrived, and have the satisfaction at the end of
my life of seeing
the beginning of my influence, it is with the hope that,
according to an old rule, it will
last the longer in proportion to the
lateness of its beginning. [p. xxviii]
Indeed, Schopenhauer's influence,
although persistent, is still limited, ironically for many
of the same
reasons that it was in his own day. The greatest value of Hegel's method
was
always that it could generate almost limitless verbiage without really saying
anything. This is invaluable for an academic career today, where journals
and books can
be filled many times over with tireless, but stupefying,
rehearsals of the same popular
shibboleths. That these will never really
mean anything to anybody -- indeed, they are
usually of the form that
nothing means anything, or that only power matters -- is far
less important
than the status, income, and, indeed, power that they foster.
What is most distressing, however, is that the moral, practical, and
intellectual
equivalent of Hegelian philosophy should have come to flourish
in great measure
because of the ascendancy of Hegel's own patron, the
Prussian State -- by which
Prussia itself, long gone, continues to live in
the institutions of welfare and police power
that all modern states have
adopted from it. Thus, compulsory public education for the
purpose for state
propaganda, the disarmament of citizens to prevent resistance to
authority,
public pensions to make everyone dependent on government ("social security"),
peacetime military conscription, and universal state identification papers
-- all originated
by Prussia -- are now supposedly enlightened features of
the so-called democracies.
Indeed, Hegel himself may have coined the word
"police" (Polizei), from the Greek word
for "state," polis. This may be the
most suitable monument of all to Hegelianism.
쇼펜하우어 ( Arthur Schopenhauer, 1788~1860)
" 世界 는 나의 表象이다."
《의지와 표상(表象)으로서의 세계》(1819)
염세사상의 대표자로 불린다. 단치히 출생. 은행가와 여류작가인 부모 덕택에 평생 생활에 걱정 없이 지냈다. 1793년 단치히가 프로이센에 병합되자 자유도시 함부르크로 이사하였고, 1803년에는 유럽 주유의 대여행을 떠났다. 1805년 그를 상인으로 만들려던 아버지가 죽자, 고타의 고등학교를 거쳐 1809년부터는 괴팅겐대학에서 철학과 자연과학을 배우고, G.E.슐체의 강의를 들었다. 이어 1811년에는 베를린대학으로 옮겨, J.G.피히테와 F.E.D.슐라이어마허를 청강하였으며, 또한 동양학자 F.마이어와의 교우(交友)로 인도고전에도 눈을 뗬다. 드레스덴으로 옮겨 4년 그러나 플라톤의 이데아론(論) 및 인도의 베다철학의 영향을 받아 염세관을 사상의 기조로 또 세계의 원인인 이 의지는 맹목적인 ‘생에 대한 의지’ 바로 그것일 수밖에 없다고 말한 그는 이와 같이, 엄격한 금욕을 바탕으로 한 인도철학에서 말하는 해탈과 정적(靜寂)의 획득 의지의 형이상학으로서는 F.W.니체의 권력의지에 근거하는 능동적 니힐리즘의 사상으로 계 |
|
'人物情報 參考' 카테고리의 다른 글
[스크랩] 칸트 ( Immanuel Kant 1724∼1804 ) (0) | 2005.08.07 |
---|---|
[스크랩] 플 라 톤(Platon) (0) | 2005.08.07 |
[스크랩] [綠野]프로이트 [Freud, Sigmund, 1856.5.6~1939.9.23] (0) | 2005.08.07 |
[스크랩] [綠野]프롬 Fromm, Erich (0) | 2005.08.07 |
[스크랩] 孔子.孟子.筍子.莊子.쇼펜하우어.몽테뉴.슈바이쳐.毛澤東.名言 (0) | 2005.08.07 |